The Human and the Absolute in the Writings of Kuki Shūzō
Essay by Maquillage Beauté Sensualité Élègance • September 14, 2015 • Essay • 5,292 Words (22 Pages) • 1,316 Views
The Human and the Absolute in the Writings of Kuki Shūzō[pic 2]
Saitō Takako
Among the metaphysical themes that interested Kuki Shūzō 九鬼周造 (1888–1941), the idea of the human person and its relation to a metaphysical absolute would seem to constitute the keystone of his phil osophical system. He dedicated several texts to this theme, in particular: Contingency 『( 偶然性』, his 1932 doctoral thesis), The Problem of Contin-
gency 『(
偶然性の問題』, 1935), “The Philosophy of Authentic Existence”
『( 実存哲学』, 1933), and “Metaphysical Time”(「形而上學的時間」, 1931). Kuki elaborated his ideas in studies of Kant, Schelling, Hegel, Heideg
ger, and Husserl, as well as in the light of a sizeable number of Chinese and Japanese texts. Any of these sources would provide interesting leads,1 but in what follows I have limited myself to elucidating the notion of the human and its relation to the metaphysical absolute by examining Kuki’s own terms and analyzing “The Philosophy of Authentic Existence” as
* The author wishes to express her gratitude to Helen Shall for preparing this
English translation from the French original.
1. Fujita (2002, 117–38) explores Kuki’s investigation and critique of Husserl’s method. For a comparison of Kuki’s three categories of contingency with Windelband and Rickert’s ideas, see Maeda 2008.
58[pic 3]
well as the two texts on contingency mentioned above. We shall also refer to one of Kant’s ideas of formal logic that Kuki took as a starting point.[pic 4]
The notion of the hum an in kuki’s works
The Human Being and “Disjunctive” Contingency
In his doctoral thesis and its subsequently expanded book, The Problem of Contingency, Kuki undertakes an exhaustive treatment of the notion of contingency. To understand the notion of the human that Kuki explains in the last part of his two texts on contingency, we begin by summarizing those texts.
Kuki opens his doctoral thesis by defining three kinds of necessity: logical, empirical, and metaphysical. Logical necessity appears in the relationship between a concept and its essential characteristics. Empiri- cal necessity is to be found in the empirical relations of cause and effect. Metaphysical necessity characterizes absolute metaphysical being
(keijijōteki zettaisha 形而上的絶對者, ksz 2: 272). In The Problem of Con-
tingency, published three years later, Kuki replaces this terminology to accommodate to the vocabular y of classical formal logic. He cites the forms of relationship between subject and predicate set out by Hermann Lotze in his Logik (1843, 65). According to Lotze, there are only three types of judgemental relations that contribute to necessary knowledge: general judgement (generalle Urtheile: s is P), hypothetical judgement (hypothetische Urtheile: on condition X, P becomes s), and disjunctive judgement (disjunctive Urtheile: a part of the whole, either P, or Q, con stitutes a predicate of s). For Kuki, these refer respectively to the rela tionship between a concept and its essential characteristics, between a necessary cause and its effect, and between the whole and any of its parts. Kuki terms these three forms categorical necessity, hypothetical necessity, and disjunctive necessity.
Following on from this, Kuki identifies three forms of contingency that negate these three relationships of necessity, categorical contingency, hypothetical contingency and disjunctive contingency (ksz 2: 15). He devotes separate parts to examining each of these. The first part considers
judgements between s and P in which the predicates are not always necessar y (categorical contingency). The second part is devoted to the analysis of the empirical events considered contingent, chance, acciden tal. Kuki terms this type of contingency hypothetical, because it requires both a condition and a consequence. In the third and final part, Kuki puts forward his thoughts on disjunctive contingency, (risetsuteki gūzen 離接的偶然), exploring specific existential situations from the perspective of the whole. He also refers to this type of contingency as metaphysical (keijijōteki gūzen 形而上的偶然).[pic 5]
This third part seems to me the most important for elucidating Kuki’s definition of the human person. In it he situates human beings within a wider whole to define them as beings that are simultaneously separate (ri 離) and in touch (setsu 接). This term “separate and in touch” is Kuki’s way of rendering into Japanese the term disjunctive taken from formal logic.2
To better understand this term, it is useful to refer to the definition found in Kant’s Logik, which was H. Lotze’s main point of reference. Judgement is there said to be disjunctive when “the parts of a given con ceptual sphere are mutually determined as a whole or complement each other to form the whole.” These judgements “are mutually exclusive and complement each other as members of the whole sphere of knowledge that has been divided.”3
...
...